In “The Present” – chapter 6 of Tinker Creek – Dillard tries to grab hold of the present moment, to divine what’s different between human and non-human experiences of time (a puppy, a tree, a man contemplating a tree, Dillard herself), to think about how consciousness and time create each other. By the second page she’s already playing with different levels of time: she travels an enormous distance in the blink of any eye (from the service station to the mountain top), then claims to see in the span of a few seconds a mountain forest advancing and retreating. Meanwhile she’s scratching the puppy and he’s experiencing the passage of time in his own way.
The difference between the puppy’s experience and Dillard’s is a crucial point for her. Consciousness, she says, allows both humans and non-humans to experience the passage of time in all its profound beauty, allows us to ride a moment in an uninterupted flow of awareness. Self- consciousness interrupts this. It makes the passage of time a series of disconnected sensory impressions. At the same time though, self-reflection, say, after a significant moment has passed, is what allows us to bring meaning to experience. At first Dillard is jealous of the puppy’s ability to surrender completely to any moment, to only be concerned with getting the most possible pleasure from her fingers on his belly. Later, though (upon reflection?), she recognizes that her experience of time is infinitely richer than the puppy’s because she has language to give it meaning. Though she’s ambivalent about this too, as she shows in her passage on Xerxes attempting to “write” the sycamore in gold so he can remember it, even though, try as he might, he’ll never get that present moment back.
But you need both. You need your self-consciousness balanced with what Dillard refers to as “innocence” – as she defines it: “the spirit’s unself-conscious state at any momet of pure devotion to any object” (pg 84 in my copy of the book). Or maybe I don’t have it quite right here. Maybe Dillard is trying to get rid of self-consciousness (as she defines it) altogether. If so, I think that move might be a little problematic, because her entire book is a balancing act of innocence and self-consciousness. A lot of what she’s doing is chronicling not just “nature” itself, but the effects of her surroundings on her consciousness, keeping track of what it means to be a thinking human in the woods. Without a large degree of self-consciousness there’d be no book.
Still, in the essay self-consciousness represents a kind of evil. Or perhaps it’s one manifestation of “evil,” or at the very least, “very bad vibes,” in this chapter. She equates self-consciousness with the worst features of city living: “Self-consciousness is the curse of the city and all that sophistication implies. It is the glimpse of oneself in a storefront window, the unbidden awareness of reactions on the faces of other people” (83). Like many artists, and many people in general, Dillard longs for a pure experience. When she quotes Stephen Graham on (my) page 81, about the golden door opening to reveal the most profound of mysteries, she claims that the door opens onto the present, onto the kind of pure experience she’s looking for, though there’s really no evidence in the text she presents that that’s what he was talking about. In fact the image and the conclusion she draws from it seem forced; I wonder if she chose it for its religious overtones.
There are other images and shifts in topic that feel forced, and all but the Golden Door seem to bring very bad vibes into the essay and to represent the opposite of that door. The first such image/shift happens on (my) page 81, when, out of nowhere, she’s talking about religion: “It is ironic that the one thing that all religions recognize as separating us from our creator – our very self-consciousness – is also the one thing that divides us from our fellow cratures. It was a bitter birthday present from evolution, cutting us off at both ends.” Indeed this passage seems cut off at both ends as there is no lead-up, and the next line is, “I get in the car and drive home,” followed by a section break. Another jarring non-sequitur pops up on pg 85, when she recalls white-coated scientists in a university lab, one dissecting a fish and the other eating a grapefruit.
I’ve gone on long enough here, and don’t know if I’ve accomplished much, but I’m interested in the way Dillard and other authors characterize time and relate it to religion and science.
Dan, do religion and time give different answers about time (and its importance?) or do you think Dillard (and possibly other writers) are somehow trying to reconcile religious and scientific treatments of time and consciousness?
ReplyDeleteThanks, Erin, for giving me a direction for my thoughts on these things. Just thinking about this quickly, it seems that in religion (maybe I should say in Christianity, since that's the only one I know well), the origin and end of time are settled. Where we come from, how we got here, the general manner in which the world as we know it will end, have all been explained. Faith and certainty are virtues. In Science, faith and certainty don't even register. In science our origin is a subject of deep speculation, and our end has nothing to do with agency of any kind and probably involves an exploding star far in the future, unless we (science) can develop the kind of technology we'd need to get out of here before that happened. Few things, if any, in science are certain. Even proven theories only enjoy that status because no one's been able to disprove them. Yet.
ReplyDeleteThis isn't to say, though, that the two are incompatible. There are plenty of religious scientists, and plenty of religious people who place a portion of their faith in science.
I'm struggling with this dichotomy Dillard has created between consciousness-sans-self and self-consciousness. As you put it, consciousness allows us to "experience the passage of time in all its profound beauty;" self-consciousness "interrupts" this, making the passage of time a series of disjointed sensory impressions.
ReplyDeleteBut is consciousness without the self even possible? And what exactly is self-consciousness? Dillard describes its effects--a separation from both our "fellow creatures" and from g/God--but she doesn't define what self-consciousness actually is. Mere awareness of the self? How can we be aware of the world, of God, without being aware that we are here, in the world, of the world, of God?
Does Dillard believe that our "fellow creatures" lack this self-awareness? And if so, why and how do they lack it? Are they beings that are fully conscious without being self-conscious? How are they able to achieve this? Why can't we?
I do not know how to be aware of the world without being aware of my self in it. I do not know how to feel God, know the object of my devotion, without knowing where that devotion comes from. It is only through my self, this mass of tissue and thought, that I am able to know something greater than my self, something that is at once me and not me.